EC 941 Game Theory Lecture 4 Prof Francesco

  • Slides: 39
Download presentation
EC 941 Game Theory Lecture 4 Prof. Francesco Squintani Email: f. squintani@warwick. ac. uk

EC 941 Game Theory Lecture 4 Prof. Francesco Squintani Email: f. squintani@warwick. ac. uk 1

Structure of the Lecture n Juries and Information Aggregation n Auctions with Private Information

Structure of the Lecture n Juries and Information Aggregation n Auctions with Private Information 2

Juries n In a trial, jurors are presented with evidence on the guilt or

Juries n In a trial, jurors are presented with evidence on the guilt or innocence of a defendant. n They may interpret the evidence differently. n Each juror votes either to convict or acquit the defendant. n A unanimous verdict is required for conviction: the defendant is convicted if and only if every juror votes to convict her. 3

n In deciding how to vote, each juror considers the costs of convicting an

n In deciding how to vote, each juror considers the costs of convicting an innocent person and of acquitting a guilty person, on the basis of her information. n When voting, she conditions her choice on being pivotal, i. e. changing the outcome of the trial. n The event of being pivotal is informative: It gives the juror information about the private information held by the other jurors, as this determines their votes. 4

A Model of Jury Vote n Each juror comes to the trial with the

A Model of Jury Vote n Each juror comes to the trial with the belief that the defendant is guilty with probability π. n Given the defendant’s status (guilty or innocent), each juror receives a signal. n The probability that the signal is “guilty” when the defendant is guilty is p, and the probability that the signal is “innocent” if the defendant is innocent is q. n Jurors are likely to interpret the evidence correctly: p > 1/2 and q > 1/2, and hence p > 1 − q. 5

n Each juror wishes to convict a guilty defendant and acquit an innocent one.

n Each juror wishes to convict a guilty defendant and acquit an innocent one. n Each juror’s payoffs are: −z if innocent defendant convicted −(1 − z) if guilty defendant acquitted. 0 if an innocent defendant is acquitted, or if a guilty defendant is convicted. 6

n Let r be the probability of the defendant’s guilt, given a juror’s information.

n Let r be the probability of the defendant’s guilt, given a juror’s information. n Her expected payoff if the defendant is acquitted is −r(1 − z) + (1 − r) · 0 = −r(1 − z) and her expected payoff if the defendant is convicted is r · 0 − (1 − r)z = −(1 −r)z. n She prefers the defendant to be acquitted if r < z, and convicted if r > z. 7

Bayesian Game of Jury Vote n Players The set of n jurors. n States

Bayesian Game of Jury Vote n Players The set of n jurors. n States The states are the set of all profiles (X, s 1, . . . , sn) where X ∈ {G, I} and sj ∈ {g, b} for every juror j. X = G if the defendant is guilty, X = I if she is innocent. si = g if player i receives the signal “guilty, ” si = b if player i receives the signal “innocent. ” 8

n Strategies The set of strategies of each player is v = {C, Q},

n Strategies The set of strategies of each player is v = {C, Q}, where C is voting to convict, and Q is voting to acquit. n Types Each player i’s type consists in a signal si together with the set of all profiles (X, s-i), where s-i denotes i’s opponents signals. 9

n Beliefs Type g of a player i believes that the state is (G,

n Beliefs Type g of a player i believes that the state is (G, s 1, . . . , sn) with probability πpk− 1(1− p)n-k and (I, s 1, . . . , sn) with probability (1−π)qk− 1(1− q)nk, where k is the number of players j (including i) with sj=g. n Type b believes that the state is (G, s 1, . . . , sn) with probability πpk(1− p)n-k-1 and (I, s 1, . . . , sn) with probability (1−π)qn-k-1(1− q)k, where k is the number of players j for whom sj = g. 10

n Payoff functions The payoff function of each player i is: ui(v, X) =

n Payoff functions The payoff function of each player i is: ui(v, X) = 0 if v = (C, . . . , C) and X=I or if v = (C, . . . , C) and X=G, ui(v, X) = −z if v = (C, . . . , C) and X = I ui(v, X) =−(1 − z) if v = (C, . . . , C) and X = G, where X is the first component of the state, giving the defendant’s true status. 11

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium n One juror Suppose there is a single juror with signal

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium n One juror Suppose there is a single juror with signal b. To see if she prefers conviction or acquittal, we find the probability Pr(G|b) that the defendant’s is guilty. By the Bayes’ Rule: Pr(G|b) = Pr(b|G)Pr(G)/[Pr(b|G)Pr(G)+Pr(b|I)Pr(I)] = (1 − p)π /[(1 − p)π + q(1 − π)]. n The juror votes Acquittal if and only if z ≥ (1 − p)π / [(1 − p)π + q(1 − π)]. 12

Suppose there are n jurors. We show that truthful voting is not a Bayesian

Suppose there are n jurors. We show that truthful voting is not a Bayesian Equilibrium. n n Suppose by contradiction that every juror other than 1 votes truthfully (acquit if her signal is b, convict if it is g). n Consider type b of juror 1. Her vote has no effect on the outcome unless every other juror’s signal is g. n Hence, she votes Acquittal if the probability Pr(G|b, g, . . . , g) that the defendant is guilty, given 13

n Specifically, Pr(G|b, g, . . . , g) = Pr(b, g, . .

n Specifically, Pr(G|b, g, . . . , g) = Pr(b, g, . . . , g|G)Pr(G) /[Pr(b, g, . . . , g|G)Pr(G)+Pr(b, g, . . . , g|I)Pr(I)] =(1 − p)pn-1π/[(1 − p) pn-1π + q(1 − q) n-1(1 − π)]. n Hence, type b of juror 1 optimally votes for acquittal if z ≥ (1 − p)pn-1π/[(1 − p)pn-1π+q(1 − q)n-1(1 − π)] = 1 /{1 +q/(1 − p) [(1 − q )/p]n-1 (1−π)/π}. n Hence, unless z is large or n is small, voting 14

n Under some conditions there is a symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium in which each

n Under some conditions there is a symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium in which each type g juror votes for conviction, and each type b juror randomizes. n Denote by β the mixed strategy of each juror of type b. n Each type b juror is indifferent between voting conviction and acquittal. n Hence the mixed strategy β is such that: z = Pr(G | signal b, n− 1 votes for C) 15

Pr(b|G)(Pr(vote C| G))n− 1 Pr(G) z= Pr(b|G)(Pr(vote C|G))n− 1 Pr(G)+Pr(b|I)(Pr(vote C|I))n− 1 Pr(I) (1−p)(p+(1−p)β)

Pr(b|G)(Pr(vote C| G))n− 1 Pr(G) z= Pr(b|G)(Pr(vote C|G))n− 1 Pr(G)+Pr(b|I)(Pr(vote C|I))n− 1 Pr(I) (1−p)(p+(1−p)β) n− 1π (1−p)(p+(1−p)β)n− 1π +q(1−q+qβ) n− 1(1 − π) n The condition that this probability equals z implies (1−p)(p+(1−p)β)n− 1π(1 − z) = q(1 − q + qβ)n− 1(1 − π)z. hence: where β = [p. X − (1 − q)] /[ q − (1 − p)X], X = {π(1 − p)(1 − z)/[(1 − π)qz]}1/(n-1). 16

n When n is large, X is close to 1, and hence β nears

n When n is large, X is close to 1, and hence β nears 1: a juror who interprets the evidence as pointing to innocence very likely nonetheless votes for conviction. n An interesting property of this equilibrium is that the probability that an innocent defendant is convicted increases as n increases: the larger the jury, the more likely an innocent defendant is to be convicted. 17

First Price Auctions n In a sealed-bid second price auction, the winner pays a

First Price Auctions n In a sealed-bid second price auction, the winner pays a price equal to second-highest bid. n In the case of complete information, this auction is strategically equivalent to the “English” auction. n In a sealed-bid first price auction, the winner pays a price equal to her bid. n This auction is equivalent to a “Dutch” auction. 18

n In a Dutch auction, the ask price for a good is decreased until

n In a Dutch auction, the ask price for a good is decreased until the one bidder accepts to buy. n Under complete information, strategic choices are equivalent in second-price auctions and Dutch auctions. n Each bidder decides, before bidding begins, the most she is willing to bid. n To win, a bidder needs to bid the highest bid, and will pay a price equal to her bid. 19

First Price Auction Game n Players: n bidders. Bidder i’s valuation is vi, we

First Price Auction Game n Players: n bidders. Bidder i’s valuation is vi, we order v 1> … > vn > 0, without loss of generality. n Strategies: bidder i’s maximal bid is bi. n Let bi = max {bj : j different from i}. n Payoffs: ui(b 1, … , bn) = 0 vi - bi if bi < bi if bi > bi 20

Nash Equilibrium One N. E. is: (b*1, … , b*n) = (v 2, …,

Nash Equilibrium One N. E. is: (b*1, … , b*n) = (v 2, …, vn). Bidder 1 wins the object, payoff: v 1 - b*1 = v 1 - v 2 > 0. If bidding b 1 < v 2, she loses the object, the payoff is 0. If bidding b 1 > v 2, her payoff is v 1 - b 2 < v 1 - v 2. The payoff of bidders i = 2, …, n is 0. If bidding bi > vi, the payoff is vi - bi < 0. If bidding bi < v 2, she loses the object, the payoff is 21

n There are many other Nash Equilibria. n In all equilibria, the winner has

n There are many other Nash Equilibria. n In all equilibria, the winner has the highest valuation. n Take any profile (b 1, . . . , bn) such that player i = 1 wins. n If bi > vi, then i’s payoff is negative, i can improve her payoff by bidding zero. n If bi < vi, then player 1 can increase her payoff from zero to v 1 - bi - e >0 by bidding bi + e. 22

Auction and Private Information n We use Bayesian games to model auctions in which

Auction and Private Information n We use Bayesian games to model auctions in which bidders do not know each others’ valuations. n If each bidder i’s type is simply her valuation vi, we say that the bidders’ values are private. If each bidder’s valuation depends also on other bidders’ types, we say that values are common. (E. g. , auctions for natural resources exploitation 23 rights). n

Second Price Auctions with Private Values n Players: n bidders. n Types: Each bidder

Second Price Auctions with Private Values n Players: n bidders. n Types: Each bidder i’s type is her valuation is vi. n Strategies: bidder i’s maximal bid is bi. Payoffs: ui(b 1, … , bn, v) = vi - bi if bi > bi 0 if bi < bi where, bi = max {bj : j different from i}. n 24

n The profile (b*1, … , b*n) = (v 1, …, vn) is the

n The profile (b*1, … , b*n) = (v 1, …, vn) is the unique weakly dominant solution. n Although valuations are now private information, the unique weakly dominant solution is the same as in the complete information case. n The proof is entirely analogous to the case of complete information. 25

Weakly Dominant Solution The strategy profile (b*1, … , b*n) = (v 1, …,

Weakly Dominant Solution The strategy profile (b*1, … , b*n) = (v 1, …, vn) is the unique weakly dominant solution. b < bi or bi < vi or bi =bi & i wins bi=bi & i loses bi > v i bi < vi vi - bi 0 0 bi = vi vi - bi 0 26

bi < vi bi = vi vi - bi bi > vi vi -

bi < vi bi = vi vi - bi bi > vi vi - bi vi < bi or bi > bi or bi =bi & i wins bi =bi & i loses 0 vi – bi (< 0) 0 0 In sum, bidding bi = vi yields at least as high a payoff as bidding bi > vi or bi < vi for any opponents’ bids. 27

First Price Auctions with Private Values n Players: n bidders. n Types: each bidder

First Price Auctions with Private Values n Players: n bidders. n Types: each bidder i’s type is her valuation vi. n Strategies: bidder i’s maximal bid is bi. n Payoffs: ui(b 1, … , bn, v) = vi - bi if bi > bi 0 if bi < bi where, bi = max {bj : j different from i}. 28

Nash Equilibrium n Say that each vi is independently drawn from a strictly increasing

Nash Equilibrium n Say that each vi is independently drawn from a strictly increasing and differentiable cumulative distribution function F, with F(v-) = 0 and F(v+) = 1. n Focus equilibria with strategies that are differentiable, increasing in the type, and symmetric across players. n To find the equilibrium, first find conditions satisfied by the players’ best response functions, 29

n n Denote the bid of type vi of player i by b(vi). The

n n Denote the bid of type vi of player i by b(vi). The expected payoff of a player of type v who bids bid b when every other player’s strategy is b is (v-b)Pr{All other bids < b} = (v-b)F(b-1(b))n-1. n To find the best response when every other player’s strategy is b, we take the first-order conditions -F(b-1(b))n-1 +(v-b)(n-1) F(b-1(b))n-2 F’(b-1(b))/b’(b- 30

n n n For (b, . . . , b) to be a Nash

n n n For (b, . . . , b) to be a Nash equilibrium, the bid b(v) must be the best response for every type of v, when every other player adopts the strategy b. I. e. , the bid b = b(v) must satisfy the previous first order conditions. Hence, the equilibrium condition is, for all v: -F(v)n-1 +(v-b(v))(n-1)F(v)n-2 F’(v)/b’(v)=0 or F(v)n-1 b’(v)+b(v)(n-1)F(v)n-2 F’(v)=v(n-1)F(v)n-2 F’(v). 31

Integrating both sides of the differential equation, v F(v)n-1 b(v)= x(n-1)F(x)n-2 F’(x) dx. vn

Integrating both sides of the differential equation, v F(v)n-1 b(v)= x(n-1)F(x)n-2 F’(x) dx. vn Integrating by parts the right hand side, v F(v)n-1 b(v) = - F(x)n-1 dx + v. F(v)n-1. vn We verify that b*(v) is increasing: (b*, …, b*) is B. N. E. , v b*(v) = v- F(x)n-1 dx/F(v)n-1. 32 vn

Revenue Equivalence Suppose that n risk neutral bidders compete in a sealed-bid auction, in

Revenue Equivalence Suppose that n risk neutral bidders compete in a sealed-bid auction, in which the highest bidder wins the good. (These auctions include first-price auctions, secondprice auctions, all-pay auctions, etc. ). n n Suppose that each bidder independently receives a signal from the same continuous and increasing cumulative distribution, and has a valuation that depends continuously on all the 33 bidders’ signals.

n Consider any symmetric Nash equilibrium with differentiable, increasing strategies, and such that the

n Consider any symmetric Nash equilibrium with differentiable, increasing strategies, and such that the expected payoff of a bidder with the lowest possible valuation is zero. n Given the opponent’s equilibrium strategies, each player’s bid affects her winning probability p and expected equilibrium payment e(p). n So, we can think of each bidder’s equilibrium bid choice as just choosing a value of p. 34

n The problem of a bidder with valuation v is: maxp pv - e(p)

n The problem of a bidder with valuation v is: maxp pv - e(p) n Let the solution be p*(v), the first-order condition gives v = e’(p*(v)) for all v. n Integrating both sides of this equation, we have v e(p*(v)) = e(p*(v-)) + x dp*(x). v 35

Because the good is sold to the bidder with the highest valuation, p*(v) =

Because the good is sold to the bidder with the highest valuation, p*(v) = Pr{vj < v, for n-1 bidders j}= Pr(X<v), where X is the highest of n-1 independent valuations. The probability of winning is independent of the detailed rules of the auction. n n Because the expected payoff of a bidder with valuation v- is zero, e(p*(v-)) = 0; hence, the expected payment of any player of type v is e(p*(v)) = Pr(X<v)E[X|X<v], independently of the 36 detailed rules of the auction.

n We obtain the following result. Theorem (Revenue Equivalence Principle). Suppose that each bidder

n We obtain the following result. Theorem (Revenue Equivalence Principle). Suppose that each bidder (i) is risk neutral, (ii) independently receives a signal from the same continuous and increasing cumulative distribution, and (iii) has a valuation that depends continuously on all the bidders’ signals. Consider auctions in which the highest bidder wins the good. Consider any symmetric Nash equilibrium with increasing strategies, and such that the expected payoff of a bidder with the lowest possible valuation is zero. The expected payment of a bidder of any given type is the same regardless of the auction rules, 37

Summary of the Lecture n Juries and Information Aggregation n Auctions with Private Information

Summary of the Lecture n Juries and Information Aggregation n Auctions with Private Information 38

Preview of the Next Lecture n Definition of Extensive-Form Games n Subgame Perfection and

Preview of the Next Lecture n Definition of Extensive-Form Games n Subgame Perfection and Backward Induction n Applications: Stackelberg Duopoly, Harris-Vickers Race. 39